Review Assignment and Note for Module G 2007
How ethical is it to displace people for reasons of development? A critical analysis of Peter Penz’s article “Development, displacement and international ethics”
by Tiina Kanninen
Development[i] projects across the globe generally aim to enhance the quality of life for people worst off. Many such projects meet their goals, hence contributing towards sustainable development. However, there are also programs that, while doing good for some end up harming others. Displacement is one of such harms. Reviewing Peter Penz’s disputable article “Development, displacement and international ethics,” I argue that, while development-induced displacement can be made morally acceptable through measures of responsibility, the situation never ethical as such. Displacing people means harming them – acting unethically towards them - and labeling such action as inherently just under any conditions only helps us to evade responsibility.
Penz divides development-induced displacement into two categories: direct and indirect. The former is directly caused by development policies, while the latter is “mediated by processes not directly under the control of decision-makers.”[ii] Often development refugees are environmental refugees. While these categories may be useful in some contexts, the distinctions are not carved in stone. Frequently development-induced displacement evolves into a “multi-dimensional syndrome of displacement,” where development-caused population movements inflict other social crises that lead to further displacement. Thus, layering itself upon the destinies of various communities, a cycle of forced migration develops and distinguishing between direct and indirect causes becomes arbitrary. Due to this complexity, no evaluation and appropriation of responsibility should be built on rationalisations of causality. This is much what Penz attempts to do.
In spite of the obvious moral dilemmas, Penz argues that under certain conditions it is justifiable to displace people for the cause of development. In order to identify such conditions, he asks what is morally owed to victims of such displacement. In his answer, Penz uses a “middle-level analysis” of applied ethics which “focuses on generalisable principles [without] commit[ting] itself to [one] particular theory.” Dialectically, he thus engages “different theoretical perspectives in a ‘dialogue’ with each other” so as to “arrive at a more sophisticated mixed position.”
The perspectives involved are utilitarianism, libertarianism and egalitarianism. Penz does not much elaborate the characteristics these ideologies and his “dialogue” remains analytically thin. Effectively, what he does is to pick and choose some definitive strengths of each position and apply them to the question of development-induced displacement. The resulting argument is that, for a development project to be morally acceptable, its environmental decision-making should be community-controlled and possible resettlements a result of “negotiations and roughly consensual consent.” This does not, however, mean “an unqualified right to veto development projects…with displacement consequences.” Instead, Penz suggests that displacement can be justified by “public interest and distributive justice considerations.” Hence, if the benefits of development are calculated as outweighing “the costs of its side-effects, including displacement,” and if these benefits be justly distributed – e.g. by maximising the conditions of the worst-off – then displacement can be deemed morally acceptable. Moreover, in the management of displacement, “certain conditions” need be met, including “compensating those displaced, minimizing displacement in the selection of development options, and giving priority to poverty alleviation in determining development strategies.”
Regardless its analytical thin-ness, the argumentation makes sense: If ever development-induced displacement can be justified, these must be the minimal measures taken. Responsibility goes with agency, however, and to ensure that the requirements be respected throughout the project and beyond, morally responsible agents must be identified. Unfortunately, Penz’s attempt to do so only leads to a listing of excuses for certain actors to evade their liability.
In
the latter half of his article, Penz evaluates foreign partners’ moral
obligations towards people displaced by development. Here, two functionally
different development partners are distinguished. These are: (1) business
organisations, whose role is “to contribute to economic production…generally
on the basis of [pursuing] profits”; and (2) “non-profit development
organisations (NGOs)[iii]
whose purpose is to advance the interests of people in development context.”
Due to their functional differences, Penz sees businesses and non-profit
organisations as operating on two different levels of responsibility - with the
latter bearing the most moral obligations while the formers’ responsibility is
kept minimum. This division becomes clear in the following quotations:
“Given
the assumption of moral…states, foreign business[es] can reasonably be
deemed to simply…obey laws…of the host state. It is the responsibility
of the host state that productive activities…do not harm people in an
unjustifiable manner. Thus, when businesses engage in logging, they need not
worry about environmental and displacement effects; that is the concern of
the state.”[iv]
“Since
there are limits to what states can do to harness economic processes to
promote…social justice, non-profit organisations have …an important role
to pursue action and innovation beyond state policy…[W]ith respect to
development-induced…displacement…they have to make the kind of broad [moral]
assessment of the causal connections between development processes and
their displacement consequences…that states ought to be making…[T]heir
moral responsibilities go considerably beyond observing the host-state law.”[v]
What
is disturbing in this line of thinking is that businesses - with their enormous
financial resources and power - can reduce their responsibilities to the
minimum, while charity based NGOs are expected to go beyond the ethical
aspirations of both states and businesses. Non-profit organisations may have a
pivotal role in the field, but when speaking about moral obligations in
development projects, surely they cannot be the major actors responsible. For
Penz they are. Adopting higher ethical standards is obligatory to businesses only
when the host state fails to do so. Moreover, whenever displacement has
“a range of causal agents,” businesses are accountable only for their
particular damage, not for the displacement. Unable to envisage ethical
responsibility as an indefinitely shareable good - that it arguably is -
Penz thus frees businesses from obligations towards those they have
“indirectly” displaced.
To conclude, Penz is right in arguing that NGOs should assess causalities between actions and their potential negative consequences, but so should all involved. Indeed, moral evaluation should be an incessant process within all development policies. Displacing people may never be ethical but, through acts of continuous, shared, inescapable and non-rational responsibility, all actors involved in such a process are obliged to make it morally acceptable. What we are talking about thus is more a question of how to be ethical in an inherently unethical situation – not how (un)ethical the situation is.
[i]
It may be a question for another essay, but it should be born in mind that
“development” is a contested concept with not only positive connotations.
As such “development” is a questionable cause of displacement indeed. Due
to lack of space, however, I have chosen not to problematise the use of the
concept in the essay.
[ii]
An example of the former would be a situation where whole communities are
evicted because of wider “developmental” goals; and of the latter, when a
“development” project deteriorates people’s living conditions so that
they must migrate for survival.
[iii]
Here, Panz uses the acronym NGO incorrectly. Although the term “non-profit
development organisation” may well describe the functions of
development-orientated NGOs, the acronym correctly used refers to nongovernmental
organisations (NGOs) of all kinds of and not just those working in
development as Penz’s term would have us understand.
[iv]
My
emphasis.
[v] My emphasis.
Ranabir
Sammadar’s article on “Power, Fear, Ethics,”
in the Refugee Watch- 14[i]
speaks about the power equation between the asylum givers vs. the asylum
seekers, fear – as a factor in displacement and ethics in law, practice and
humanitarian issues towards the issues of refugees and displaced.
The
factor “fear” affects the displaced population in all phases of
displacement- initially the person flees from his place of habitual residence
out of fear, lands in an alien environment which according to Judge Geoffery
are (as Sammadar says) “frequently hostile and incredulous” which leads to
constant fear and it is also fear that effects their return- both in
decisions and practice.
Firstly
I’d like to add that the states have their own rules on defining who is a
refugee or an internally displaced person (IDP)[ii]-
and this is often the cause for fear itself. For eg: Nepal’s IDP policy till
very recently only recognized only those people whose family members were
killed or whose houses/properties were destroyed by the Maoist – only
Maoist (the revolting party) as an “IDP”. The state mechanism- which
are by far very weak and absurd, were to determine who among all its people
were Maoists. Firstly even those who were displaced by Maoists had to have
physical evidence that they had really suffered physical losses; those who
were displaced for psychological causes, perceived and real were not regarded
as IDPs. Secondly those who were displaced due to the actions of security
forces were not regarded as IDPs- in a situation where the security forces
often operated beyond the confines of any laws, humanity or dignity. And
thirdly the populations who were displaced because they were caught between
the warring sides- which make the most of the displaced population, were not
regarded as IDPs. So those
displaced people of the above mentioned second and third categories had fear
from the state itself that by the international prerogatives of sovereignty
had the fore and the foremost responsibility of protecting and providing for
them. Such, as displacement studies show, is the case not only in Nepal but in
most conflict situations where civilians are always never distinguished from
the combatants and thus live in constant fear from all warring sides.`
Needless
to say, with his vast knowledge
and experience Sammadar has analyzed minutely and portrayed the dilemma of
displaced population very efficiently with his style of writing- that brings
pictures (of the written examples) in my mind. Even for those fortunate among
the displaced who are at least recognized by the law-in its written form as
right to get refuge, taking into account their psychological and physical
state, find it very hard to prove that there is a “well grounded fear”-
the clause set by 1951 Convention and ratified by most states, as mandatory to
get the status of refugee. The measure of fear as to how “well grounded”-
with all its complication as shown by Sammadar’s article and discussed
incoming paragraphs is again done by the states’ judicial and legal
mechanisms- probably by those people who have never experienced the situations
themselves thus never knowing what to look for and how to interpret the
symptoms shown by people in fear, among other forms of analysis.
In
the situation, fear and exclusion comes in all phases and colors.
Firstly there is a bias in the level of access- as to who approach the
state for asylum. Most of the people who approach the state are those who have
information on the facilities ie the elites, able, literate and other less
vulnerable groups who are not afraid of or at least familiar with
the state functioning.
Those who do not have information and access are primarily those of the
illiterate, rural, single women, and myriad of other vulnerable population who
are apprehensive of the states apparatus. For them the action of approaching
the state for help itself needs a great victory over fear.
Next
groups who have a sound knowledge of law and judiciary requirement can easily
“word” their conditions to match it as required by the law and thus
benefit the status. This is the reason why there is a group in Nepal (which I
shamefully confess) consisting even of top level ministers who have a well
equipped bungalow in Kathmandu city- the capital, have been living here with
their family members for decades and are now enjoying the benefits of IDPs-
where records have been made to show that they were displaced from some remote
village of Nepal. On the other hand, the vulnerable group when confronted with
the arrogance and scrutinizing ogle of the state where the judge- who probably
can never imagine himself on the shoes of the refugee as Sammadar rightly says
“ The judge changes gradually from a recipient of request to an interrogator
of grounds, who arrogates to him the sovereign authority to interpret, assess,
and declare the past pain of the refugee and his fear of future torture”
mostly fail to verbalize their true conditions which consequently leads to the
denial of refugee status. Also
significant is the biasness inheriting in the Judge- who as a human being is
subject to effects like his own conscious or unconscious perceptions on race,
caste and ethnicity, place of origin, literacy etc, working environment and
myriad of other factors which may come to marginalize the already vulnerable
population.
The
refugee who flees from the adversaries of his state to a system where s/he is
alien to confronts the international system which tries to frame the rule of
who is a refugee and how is he to be treated thus living in constant fear from
the same system which gives them refuge.
Above
all “ Fear” itself is an abstract phenomenon and trying to measure how
well grounded it is, is itself
a critical process which however competent the system may claim to be
can always be questioned. For to what extent does one perceive fear and who
and how one perceives fear depends on the psychological and psychosocial
environment or status of each individuals. Psychological state itself is
dependent on history of generations of his family to present condition of the
individual and countless other factors. So just to examine whether an
individual’s fear is well grounded or not through a series of questions or
short observations (if there really is) during a critical period by a system
which has its own shortcomings is something that really needs a second
thought.
Caught
in this web of absurdities and mostly with no or little supportive
requirements the refuge seeker is confused, traumatized and nervous- the
vulnerable within them more so. This also leads to further change in power
equations- with the rise of power of asylum givers over the seekers as
Sammadar says” fear reinforces the exercise of power”
Thus as Sammadar and the editorial of this issue of Refugee Watch says “that while the 20th century might have taught the world to deal systematically with vast refugee flows, too many to count precisely, 21st century might have to invent new ways of coping with them with the changing nature and definition of refugee crises” and there it is important to analyze how fear pivots around and affects the displaced population – by the way in which how it is defined and utilized, how it is constructed and institutionalized around certain social identities, how it is reflected in experience and practices around the theme of refugee, and political and social practices towards them.
[i]
The article is a part of an inaugural lecture given in a seminar on
population movement ad population displacement in Shillong on 12-13 July,
2001.
[ii] In this writing I stick to the definition of IDP as in the Guiding Principles of Internal Displacement (Deng, 1998) and Refugee –as a person who due the same condition has crossed an internationally recognized border of his home country. By “displaced population” I mean both of this status.
Power, ethics and fear (case of Georgia) – an Essay
by Iulia Kharashvili
The
situation of displacement brings many challenges in all areas, starting from
humanitarian assistance, necessary for primary survival of those displaced,
satisfying their elementary needs. In situation of emergency these needs are
manifested as the main, and both, governmental assistance in the framework of
claimed responsibility and assistance provided privately, are very important.
On the latest stages, more responsibility lays on the power structures,
including national and local
governments, international organizations, even in case of internal
displacement the primary responsibility belongs to the national authorities.
Looking on the case of internal displacement in Georgia, it is possible to tackle some of dilemmas, related with ethical considerations. The issues, which were not fully relevant during the emergency period, become crucially important in case of protracted refugee or IDP situation.
In
situations of displacement, related with the massive violence and military
actions, the important dilemma for me is one stressed in the article of
Dr. By Ranabir Samaddar – the division of responsibility between the
state - recipient and those
authorities/states which actually exiled people. The right to return to the
homes/ places of habitual residences envisaged
in international law, is questioned
in many cases by subjective orders, decrees and documents issues by
local authorities in postconflict zones. The clear indication about full
responsibility of national authorities for the destiny and well being of IDPs
is given in the Guiding Principles of Internal Displacement. Even the Guiding
Principles are not the legally binding document, such as Convention or
Covenant, there belong to the
‘Soft law’ instruments, ‘thus occupying the grey zone between law and
politics’ (David Fisher, in the book ‘Internal Displacement in South
Asia’).
The
Government of Georgia adopted the Guiding Principles, however often it
infringes rights stated in the Guiding Principles, and interprets the
‘responsibility’ of national authorities by such way, which allows it to
manipulate the IDPs, including for the political reasons. Thus for many
years IDPs had continued to stay in limbo, nor permitted to return by de
facto authorities, neither – fully to integrate, and their desperate
living and socio-economic conditions had been used as an argument in
political negotiations, however, the IDP s themselves for years were kept
under the same conditions ‘not to lose motivation to return’.
There
are several dilemmas facing now by the IDP community – the first is the
dilemma of return to habitual residences/homes vs
integration.
As
it was noted by the UN Secretary General Special Representative on IDP Human
Rights Dr. Walter Kalin in his
Statement concerning the situation of IDPs in Georgia (December 2005), the
local integration in current places of living should not affect the right to
return.
Certainly,
the right to return is n inherent right. From more than quarter of million
of internally displaced in Georgia, about 50 m- 60 thousands are seasonably
migrating across the de facto borders
– to work their lands and to collect their harvest. It happens only in the
Gali district, located near de facto border. The territories of this
spontaneous return are not under jurisdiction nor of central Government,
neither de facto authorities,
that creates the deficit of power, lack of security and absence of rule of
law.
Unclear
situation of these returnees leads to the lack of clear definition of their
status (they still are called the IDPs as there is no security, they don’t
stay permanently and don’t rehabilitate their houses due to fear of being
robbed or kidnapped). They cannot be called spontaneous returnees in full
scale, as they are forced to return by miserable socio-economic conditions
in the place of temporary living, may be they
can be called presumed, even they physically temporarily are there.
As no physical, psychological, informational and material security cannot be
ensured and no power (nor governmental, neither international organisations)
take responsibility for IDPs security, the IDPs status cannot be removed
from them.
The
central Government (Government of Georgia) have very limited possibilities
to care about those IDPs who
are living in the postconflict zone and to express to them sympathy and
support – mainly through small assistance in education and health
programmes. The de facto authorities prevent the involvement of Georgia
central Government in solving of problems of IDP population.
At
the same time, often some officials express mistrust towards those who lives
in postconflict zones and announce them as betrayers of own people. It
created additional fears and tension for IDPs living in Gali district –
they afraid to leave the postconflict zone and stay in Georgia proper
constantly as in such case they cannot ensure enough food for their
families, and they are frightened by local de facto authorities and
criminals acting in the Gali district, at the same time, they cannot fully
rely on protection from the central Government, because they did not control
situation and sometimes have double standards toward spontaneous returnees.
According
to the cease fire agreement, signed by the sides (Georgia and Abkhazia with
the mediation of Russia and UNHCR) in 1994, persons from Georgian side, who
participated in military actions, have no immunity in
case of return, thus, could not return also if the procedure of
repatriation will start. This agreement
did not differentiate persons, who were protected lives of their families,
from those who were involved in the war crimes.
Using in this case all sentiments, humanitarian and also community
approach, it is possible to advocate for changing of this statement and
creating of community based mechanisms, similar to Reconciliation and
Justice and Truth Commissions, which will deal in case of return case by
case and will assist to ex-combatants, if they were not involved in cruel
actions and crimes against humanity, to return.
Absence
of such article psychologically deprives many of IDPs from even theoretical
chance to return, as members of families of ex-combatants also will be not
able to return and leave behind their husbands, brothers and sons. Till now,
the opportunity to return is accessible only
for small number of IDPs – former inhabitants of border
Gali region, for others this opportunity did not exist even
virtually. This makes IDPs more vulnerable and dependent on assistance,
provided by the Government, society members and international organizations.
The
difference between caring about IDP
community as a whole (including provision of state allowances,
medical insurance certificates, provision of temporary shelter) and
covering of needs of individual IDPs is very visible at community level. In
beginning of displacement, ordinary citizens from local community tried to
provide assistance and care for those displaced. Till now, more than 55% of
IDPs continue to live with the relatives, friends and known people, who
provide for them shelter. Other
45 % are looked after by the Government. Such phenomena supports
in IDP community syndrome of dependency, and creates sometimes
the local population attitude to IDPs as to fully vulnerable
community.
To overcome these obstacles, including isolation and non-inclusion of IDPs, lack of social capital and dependency syndrome, in 2006 the Government of Georgia announced creation of IDP State Strategy, which should serve two main purposes: preparation for return and the improvement of socio-economic and living conditions of IDPs. It is expected that such Strategy can contribute to raising of civil conciseness among IDPs, from one hand, and, from another hand, will increase the responsibility of national authorities, support psychologically and empower the IDPs for giving them chance for dignified lives bothm in case of return and integration.
Importance of Ethics and Justice in Rehabilitation and Care of Refugees
by Magdalena Sikora
“...recognition
of the inherent dignity and of the equal and inalienable
rights of all members of the human family is the foundation of
freedom, justice and peace in the world.”[i]
The
purpose of this review note is to elaborate the importance of ethics and justice
in rehabilitation and care of refugees. This note is based on the relevant
sections of “International Refugee
Law: A Reader” of B.S. Chimni.
There
is no doubt in the statement that refugee flow
has become one of the most pressing humanitarian, human rights and security
problems confronting the international community.
The
causes of refugee displacement can be internal and international. Therefore, the
refugee phenomenon is an element of the complex group of international relations
among states which present the growing reciprocal interdependence and necessity
of taking common steps for general interest of international community. This
kind of global solidarity sets up the co-responsibility for both the causes of
refugee flows and the solutions dealing with the rehabilitation and care of this
group of displaced people. The international co-responsibility should be based
on ethics[ii]
and international justice[iii]
which is guaranteed for every human being. In the context of refugee
displacement the question arises what importance the action of international
community following the assumption of ethics and international justice has for
the protection, rehabilitation and care of refugees.
Analyzing
ethics and global justice in the concept of refugee rehabilitation and care, it
is clearly demonstrated that they propagate first and foremost the equality of
all human beings with no difference of their actual status. There is no ethical
and philosophical justification for a nation to employ different standards for
the treatment of its own citizens and those from other countries. It does not
mean that state should always treat non-nationals in the same manner as its own
citizens, but the evaluation criteria of its actions must be the same.[iv]
In
addition, as Beyani
argues according to Principle 1 of the International Law Association’s
Declaration of Principles of International Law on Compensation to Refugees, the
responsibility for caring for the world’s refugees rests ultimately upon
countries that directly or indirectly force their own citizens to flee/or remain
abroad as refugees. The discharge of such responsibility by countries of asylum,
international organizations and donors shall not relieve the countries of origin
of their basic responsibility. The Inter-American Court of Human Rights has
elaborated upon this doctrine in the context of human rights. In its view, the
State has the right and duty to guarantee its security without question, but its
power is not unlimited. Nor may a State resort to any means to attain its ends;
the State is subject to law and morality, and disregard for human dignity cannot
serve as a basis of any State action.[v]
However, as Singer states, we persist in thinking of foreign aid as a
„charity”, which means that we do well if we give it, but we are not subject
to blame or reproach if we do not. We see ourselves as under no obligation to
save the starving of Africa or Asia, even if doing so would entail not real
sacrifices at all.[vi]
However,
it should be emphasized that it has been already developed the complex system of
the legal and institutional tools which deal with the displacement of refugees,
their rehabilitation and care, i.e. the 1951 Convention relating to the Status
of Refugees and the United Nations High Commissioner for Refugees (UNHCR).
However, in many circumstances when they present the essential gaps in proposing
the adequate solution for the protection of refugees, the international
community should follow the assumptions of ethics and justice. It must be also
added that the national migration policy may be good on some level, but from the
ethics and justice perspective it is very often seen as a destructive direction.
First and foremost, when it concerns rigorous asylum procedures, closing of
borders, refoulment etc.
Based on this concise review and following the opinion of Peter and Renata Singer, we can conclude that it would not be difficult for the nations of the developed world to move closer to fulfilling their moral obligations to refugees. There is no objective evidence to show that doubling their refugee intake would cause them any harm whatsoever. Much present evidence, as well as past experience, points the other way, suggesting that they and their present population would probably benefit.[vii] The international refugee law includes some gaps and obscurity which can often be solved by referring to the extralegal, ethical arguments. The best way to manage the problem of refugee flows seems to be taking a common effort and stimulating an international cooperation based not only on legal and political instruments, but on ethics and global justice as well. There are liberal conceptions of universal rights and international justice to justify the claims of refugees. And as the United Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights states: “All human beings are born free and equal in dignity and rights. They are endowed with reason and conscience and should act towards one another in a spirit of brotherhood." And the refugees are not an exception.
[i]
Preamble to the Universal Declaration
of Human Rights, 1948.
[ii]
Ethics seen as the study of values
and customs
of a person or group. It covers the analysis
and employment of concepts
such as right
and wrong,
good
and evil, and responsibility.
[iv]
In practice, however, there is a
frequent conflict between refugee rights and national interests and instead of
application of universal rights, it exists the phenomenon of avoiding the
obligations to non-nationals.
[v]
A. Chaloka Beyani, “State Responsibility for the Prevention and Resolution
of Forced Population Displacements in International Law”, International
Journal of Refugee Law (Special Issue, 1995), p. 131-37.
[vi]
Singer Peter, „Famine, Affluence and Morality”, Philosophy and Public
Affairs, 1972, p. 229-243.
[vii]
Singer Peter and Renata, „The Ethics of Refugee Policy”, in „Open Borders?
Closed Societies? The Ethical and Political Issues”, edited by Mark Gibney,
1988, p. 121.
Review relevant sections on ‘ethics’ and ‘justice’ in B.S.Chimni’s ‘International Refugee Law: A reader’ and comment on the importance of these two issues in the rehabilitation and care of refugees.
by Marini de Livera
The
ethics and justice sections of the reader speak of Human Rights and duties of
the refugees. The reader also sets out landmark cases where key words such as
‘refugee’, ‘well-founded fear’ and ‘persecution’ are judicially
interpreted.
However, with regard to the actual rehabilitation and care of the refugees it is difficult to affirm that these concepts are translated into practical terms.
The
reader opens with an indication of the importance of the definition of the
refugee. The ordinary meaning of he word’ refugee’ is contrasted with the
clear cut international law definition of refugee. Also a distinction is drawn
between ‘a refugee’ and an ‘internally displaced person. When determining
what is morally acceptable, ethical and fair it is necessary to begin by asking
‘who exactly a refugee is’. Chimni’s reader succinctly defines the term
and analyses the key words included in the definition. Vital phrases such as
‘well founded fear’ and ‘systematic persecution’ are examined in depth.
International and Domestic Law makers are generally ‘gender blind’. Although
the criteria for determining refugee status set out in the 1951 Convention
ignores gender, the reader has included erudite articles such as that written by
Jacqueline Great batch, on the Feminist critiques of the refugee discourse. The
article highlights the favorable attitude of the European Parliament and the
UNHCR to the voices of the Feminists critics to the fact that women who face
‘harsh and inhuman treatment’ are utterly bereft.
The
third Chapter of the reader deals with the Rights and Duties of Refugees. The
extract from Robin Nedham’s article on ‘Refugee participation’ is very
realistic and practical. As a social worker who was involved in the
rehabilitation and care of Tsunami affected Sri Lankans I would wholeheartedly
agree with every word written by him.
Also
of vital importance are the observations and conclusions of the participants of
the tenth Round Table on Current Problems of International Humanitarian Law.
Chimni
also focuses on Refugee Children by reminding the readers that refugee children
too are covered by the Rights of the Child Convention.
As
the great Mahatma Gandhi wrote in a letter to Julian Huxley who then the
Director- General of UNESCO, at the time of the preparation by the United
Nations of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, “I learnt” he
wrote,” from my illiterate by wise mother that all rights
to be deserved and preserved came from duty well done.”
Similarly
B.S. Chimni has not relegated duties to the background. The duties of refugees
too are enumerated under the heading duties and fundamental rights.
Now,
it is interesting to see how the principles on ethics and justice can be
integrated into the rehabilitation and care of refugees.
The
gap between reality and the ideal is very wide.
For
ethics and justice to be integrated into the process of rehabilitation and the
care of refugees it is assumed that those working on rehabilitation and involved
in the care of refugees are armed with adequate knowledge of internationally
accepted norms relating to this. Also states dealing with refugees should have a
clear policy with regard to the right to choose on where they would like to
live. To be effective the rehabilitation programmes should include efficient
community services, education,
sanitation and legal assistance. Trade, physical mobility and development work
should be carried out unrestricted in the rehabilitated areas. It is also
essential that there is a channel of communication between the affected people
and the government. Also machinery should be in place to empower the affected
group to participate in decision-making at village level. The government
agencies, NGOs, community-based organizations and civil society should network
and coordinate in the relief and rehabilitation effort.
Further,
accurate statistical information relating to the refugees should be made
available. A clear and coherent strategy with regard to the rehabilitation and
the care of refugees should be drawn up.
The
existing domestic legislation should be reviewed focusing on possible
inconsistencies and a comprehensive analysis of Human rights and humanitarian
law should be taken into account, identifying mechanisms and measures to rectify
them.
Attention
should be paid to rights of disabled refugees, to protection, to liberty and to
the security of the person, to humanitarian assistance and to their resettlement
and integration into society.
Where
refugees are unable to register as voters and do not have any voting rights; the
government should take the necessary steps to rectify this issue.
It
is important to protect existing development assets whether in the form of
infrastructure or social and economic processes. There exists a close link
between relief work, rehabilitation and development. Humanitarian work must be
conducted in a manner that does not create dependencies or frustrate future
rehabilitation efforts.
In
the interest of transparency and accountability, an independent humanitarian
ombudsman system should be established to channel complaints and grievances from
beneficiaries, from affected community-based organizations and from the public
and from agencies dealing with relief, rehabilitation and the care of refugees.
Also
the different needs of women and children have to be taken into account along
the lines set out in Chimni’s reader.
In order to eradicate discrimination there should be a change in outlook and thinking. Government, Civil society and all those who are involved in the care and rehabilitation of refugees must understand the plight of these people and must not show partiality and discrimination in any form.
Critically analyse Peter Penz’s article on “Development, Displacement and international Ethics”, and comment how ethical it is to displace people for reasons of development?
by Ishita Dey
In
this essay, I want to analyse Peter Penz’s theoretical construct of
“cosmopolitan ethics” and whether or not “cosmopolitanism” approach can
determine the moral obligation of the foreign participants in the development
process. Peter Penz argues that the foreign participants in the localized
development process should be bound to follow the rules of the state. While Penz
is not blind to the internationalized production process in what he calls “the
increasing economic, cultural and political integration of the world”; he
should also recognize that there exists a hierarchy within this production
process itself.
The
hierarchy is reproduced in the very notion of development that considers
displacement as an integral component and assumes that the “state” should be
responsible for “environmental and displacement effects” and “foreign
business organizations” should have the responsibility to obey the laws of the
state. The “host state” like Penz rightly points out often acts as the
“mediator between the foreign actor and the state citizens”.
The host state is not exclusive of the overarching global politics. The
third world has been the testing ground of a top-down approach to development
which has led to enormous displacement. The displaced in most of the cases have
not enjoyed the fruits of development and it is against this background that the
ethics of displacement for reasons of development should be analysed.
Those
displaced due to construction of Bhakra Nangal dam have been forced to resettle
in areas where they do not enjoy basic drinking water facility. Bhakra is one of
the many cases in a country which has been witness to many a policy exercises of
resettlement and rehabilitation. The recent NRP 2006 which primarily addresses
the issue of development induced displacement speaks of people’s involvement
in the R&R process post land acquisition and not when the land is been
acquired which reflects the accountability of the state. It is only when the
state will be accountable towards its citizens can we talk of the “moral
responsibility” of the foreign business houses as Penz proposes. In case of
resistance movements against the recent move to acquire land for SEZ in Bengal,
Maharashtra and Orissa one of the primary concerns of the protesters was the
question of alternative livelihood, home and land. In case of mining projects it
is the tribals who are the worst affected. Kudremukh Mining project made it to
the news when the Government decided to extend the lease to KIOCL despite the
repeated protests by the environmental groups and locals. The tribals are
reportedly being killed under the garb of the Naxalites. These instances are
some food for thought to reflect on whether or not it is ethical to displace
people for reasons of development. Most of the cases of recently proposed land
acquisitions in Orissa be it by POSCO or Vedanta the nation- state to attract
FDI has chosen to take sides of the foreign actors. Under such conditions one is
quite skeptical regarding the “cosmopolitan approach” as it is finally
through the “language of rights” that one can “empower the local/ host
communities” to redefine their nature of “hospitality and shelter”[i]
which opens up another dimension as far as the “ethics” of moral
responsibility is concerned.
The
“ethics” of “moral responsibility” is best put into practice when the
concerns of those displaced are seen within the purview of the “language of
rights” or “right to life” rather than as a notion of “moral
responsibility” without any legal binding. More than “moral justification”
as Peter Penz argues in the first half of the essay that underlies displacement
one could read the “justifications” behind displacement as three approaches
to development. When one tries to delineate “justification of displacement”
it considers displacement as inevitable and it is there the dialectical nature
of displacement and development regarding its ethical character gets far more
explicit. The three perspectives are public- interest perspective, self
-determination perspective which treats freedom and choice as central and
equal-sharing perspective which sees development as reducing inequalities. Self
-determination perspective and equal-sharing perspective treats the rights of
individual and community as central and it is this prioritization that creates a
unique approach to development which will minimize displacement and provide
adequate resettlement and rehabilitation to those displaced.
Recognition of rights will inevitably change the “power” game that underlies the very decision of “moral responsibility” and specifically the first concern of Peter Penz as to what do we morally owe to the potential and actual victims of displacement? What we morally owe to those affected should be decided by the “language of rights” as our experience with the past and the resistance movements against proposed land acquisitions for development in Maharashtra, Orissa, Andhra Pradesh and Uttar Pradesh have shown.
[i] Ranabir Samaddar in the ‘Introduction’ to the Refugees and the State: Practices of Asylum and Care in India, 1947-2000 argues that one of the challenges to cosmopolitanism is to make sentiments meaning (tolerance, democracy and nationalism) relevant for the host communities in response to guests from near abroad. He argues that the language of rights should be the overarching state discourse towards refugees rather than of tolerance and sentiments.
A critical discussion of “fear” as a factor in the displacement of vulnerable groups
by Sriram Haridass
The
problems of the world’s displaced are among the most complicated issues before
the international community today. Much discussion is taking place at the
global, regional and national levels as we continue to search for more effective
ways to protect and assist these particularly vulnerable groups.
While some call for increased levels of cooperation and coordination among relief agencies, others point to gaps in international legislation and appeal for further standard setting in this area. In this debate some facts remain beyond dispute. To begin with while some mass displacements may be preventable, none are voluntary. No one likes or chooses to be a displaced. In some instances being a displaced means more than being an alien. It means living in exile and depending on others for such basic needs as food, clothing and shelter.
Why
would then some one leave his or her home in favor of an uncertain life
elsewhere in a foreign land? In 2004, Moore and Shellman tried to answer this
question by studying a global sample of countries over more than forty years.
Their findings indicated that violent behavior resulting in “fear” has a
substantially larger impact on displacement and forced migration of vulnerable
groups than any other factor.
The
concept of “well founded fear” also plays an important role in the refugee
definition. But unfortunately the linguistic ambiguity in the refugee
definition’s requirement of “well-founded fear” of being persecuted has
given rise to a wide range of interpretations and over the years the concept has
been a subject of debate among refugee advocates and national refugee
determination bodies.
There
is general agreement that a fear is “well-founded” only if the refugee
claimant faces an actual, forward-looking risk of being persecuted in her
country of origin (the “objective element”). But it is less clear whether
the well-founded “fear” standard also requires a showing that the applicant
is not only genuinely at risk, but also stands in trepidation of being
persecuted (Hathaway & Hicks, 2005). In 2004, the University of Michigan Law
School engaged in sustained collaborative study and reflection on the doctrinal
and jurisprudential foundations of the well-founded fear standard. They
concluded that continued reference to distinct “subjective” and
“objective” elements of the well-founded fear standard risks distortion of
the process of refugee status determination. As Ranabir
Samaddar points out
the current international refugee protection regime leaves a great burden on
jurisprudence and enormous freedom to the state in interpreting the “well
founded fear” concept. This argument is also supported by Hathaway (1991) who
states that the approach of states to the concept of well founded of fear is
neither historically defensible nor practically meaningful. As a result of this
enormous freedom enjoyed by states in interpreting the concept of “fear”,
many of the modern day displaced persons are not seen to fall within the
definition contained in 1951 convention.
In
1951, when the refugee convention was adopted, most of the refugees originated
from Europe. The situation has changed and the majority of today’s refugees
are from Africa and Asia. Current refugee movements unlike those of the past
increasingly take the form of mass exoduses rather than individual flights and
majority of today’s refugees are women and children. The causes of exodus have
also multiplied and now include natural/ecological disasters and extreme poverty
which are not accepted as valid reasons for displacement by the international
protection regime and the 1951 convention.
Refugee
law scholars like Ranabir
Samaddar feel that the contemporary humanitarian refugee regime has got
institutionalized and the 1951 convention has failed to negotiate the population
flow of the world today. The
UNHCR’s protection Chief Erika Feller agrees. According to her “UNHCR’s
perception is that refugee protection stands at a crossroads. Its most important
tool—the 1951 Convention—sets out a basic framework that remains directly
relevant to many, but not to all,
displacement situations.”
Refugee
protection today is confronted by a number of major challenges and experts agree
that the refugee protection regime needs an immediate transformation. There are
repeated calls nowadays to revisit and revise the 1951 convention so that the
population flow could be better managed. On the other hand some refugee scholars
fear that if the convention is put in any way into discussion, we may end up
with a convention and a protection regime of much more limited rights. Refugee
advocates White and Rowman (2007) argue
that states are also keen on amending the 1951 convention partly in
response to the rise in criminal trafficking across borders, and partly in an
attempt to better balance the refugee’s well founded fear of persecution with
the demands for increased security aftermath the 9/11 incident.
However
fearing negative consequences and not revising the current refugee protection
set up and 1951 convention might not be the right way to go about. The need for
change in the refugee protection regime is being felt more than ever and
reforming processes are essential to resolve or mitigate the factors/causes
resulting in forced migration and displacement, and especially to end protracted
displacement situations. It is now or never for the international protection
regime and if they continue to prolong the change process we will be really “seeing
the last act in an opera on the death of emotions”.
References
Hathaway,
The Law of Refugee Status (Toronto: Butterworths, 1991), 69-97
Hathaway
& Hicks, ’Is There a Subjective Element in the Refugee Convention’s
Requirement of Well-Founded Fear?’ (2005) 26 Michigan Journal of
International Law 505.
White
& Rowman , ‘Fear of Persecution: Global Human Rights, International
Law, and Human Well-Being’, Littlefield
Publishers, Inc., 2007.
Will H. Moore & Stephen M. Shellman, ‘Fear of Persecution: Forced Migration, 1952-95’ Journal of Conflict Resolution, October 2004, 48(5):723-745
Review relevant section on ethics and justice in B.S. Chimni’s International Refugee Law: A Reader and comment on the importance of these two issues in rehabilitation and care of refugees.
by James Ward Khakshi
Introduction
For
refugee study, ethics and justice are two important terms always more relevant
than that of other cases. Because here identifying refugees, providing justice,
rehabilitation and care to them all are firstly dependent on the ethics of the
state liable for origin and states relevant for creating or caring the refugees.
B.S. Chimni in his edited book
International Refugee Law: A Reader has unconsciously drawn the analytical
form of this matter in the different sections of the book.
International
Refugee Law: A Reader
edited by B.S. Chimni has been divided into eight chapters. Identifying refugee,
UNHCR, causes of refugee flow, exemplified durable solutions through legal and
ethical point of view and means, discussion on Internally Displaced People and
the legal condition of refugees in India are the structural division of the
book. Here he collected the laws relating to refugees and their analysis with
relevant reference. In every chapter of the book, the discussion of ethics and
justice very often in rehabilitation and care has got notice in conscious or
unconscious.
Relevant
sections on ethics and justice
Ethics
and justice in caring refugees are very important concepts. B.S. Chimni in the
first chapter shows the general tendency of states and international bodies to
set the refugee status within a strictly defined legal context, seeking to
portray the phenomenon of refugee hood as reducible to a legal definition. Much
rests upon their interpretation of the 1951 Geneva Convention relating to the
status of refugees. States interpret who are refugees and who are suitable for
protection and care. Chapter two discusses how asylum of refugees, their
protection and care depends on the whimsical interpretation of refugees by
states. Chapter five shows multidimensional causes of refugee flow and the law
of state responsibility in this regard. It very rightly accommodates political,
economic environmental, ethnic, human rights abuse and the inter-related link as
a cause of refugee flow. In most cases, the ethical orientation of the state,
the security pretext of the state and the regional and international link get
the priority concern as a cause of refugee flaw. Chapter six discusses the
different approaches of repatriation for durable solution of refugee issue.
Chapter seven comprises laws relating to the internally displaced persons and
its multidimensional analysis. UNHCR is being active to draw the issue. Every
state know the causes of the internally displaced persons. Solution thus largely
depends on the good governance of the state and the ethical orientation of the
state concerned.
Importance
of ethics and justice in rehabilitation and care of refugees
Statist
ethics involves two levels or stages of moral consideration. One is that of
intra-state ethics and the other is that of inter-state ethics. The statist
ethics (both levels) determines who is their citizen and who would not be their
citizen and thus will be alienated and refugees will be created. The ethics and
the justice system of a state is the moral basis of the political system of a
state and determinant how it will behave to refugees originated from or come to
the state. Chapter two discusses the principle of Non-refoulement
while chapter six is on different repatriation options. Here the issue of
rehabilitation is discussed where it is also noticed that ethics and justice
system (neutral and effective or not) of the states are the curtained issue to
success the rehabilitation process.
Conclusion
To
ensure rehabilitation and care for refugees, the necessary condition is not only
the ethic of care, kindness, and hospitality, but also an added ethic, that of responsibility.
Responsibility has two implications - responsibility of the state and of the
international community. The word, responsibility, carries two senses
also - responsibility of the host and that of the expelling state. Justice
system of a state is closely determined by the ethics and political system of
the state. So dealing with the rehabilitation and care of refugees, the ethics
and justice is very important. B.S. Chimni in his book did not intensify the
matter. But it could be easily identified by critical biased study of the book.
For refugee issue, we finally have to understand that no amount of diplomacy or international safeguards will be succeed in preventing population displacement if a state based on majoritarianism is determined to violate the rights of the people. To compromise the hegemonic mentality of majority, the (liberal) legal provision and neutral policy among many conditions are crucially important. But in all cases the internal matter affecting the decision and policy of the states is the ethics and justice (system) of the states (statist ethics). The editor did not purposely discuss the ethical orientation of the states to discuss the legal provision affecting the refugees of the world. But this was felt in the successive chapters of the book.
Review of Peter Penz essay on Development, Displacement and International Ethics
by Francis Adaikalan
Peter
Penz tries to distinguish between
direct and indirect displacement. He suggests that it is very difficult to
compartmentalize in some circumstances, like environmental refugees. But
majority of the displacement in today’s world increasingly becoming complex in
which one cannot distinguish between direct or indirect displacement. In those
circumstances the state conveniently stays away or sheds away its
responsibilities by terming such a displacement as indirect. For example,
displacement due to industrial policy and by announcing a particular corridor as
industrial belt brings forceful displacement for many.
As penz points out straight jacketing or compartmentalizing between
voluntary and forced migration will result in more insensitive way of dealing
with people. Because in present
circumstances the choices are limited since most of the displacement are
coerced. For example, even though there is resistance from the people against
Koodumkulam atomic power station in Tamilnadu, the state went ahead with its
plan. So how can one justify the displacement due to development since it is
morally objectionable as author puts it?
Penz
argued that it is difficult to address the issue of displacement from
theoretical per se since there are internal conflicts among the theoreticians.
The policy makers in his opinion show less interest such philosophical
differences. But he failed to explain the phenomenon that most of the time their
actions are based on some ideological position.
Secondly
he said that contextual specific focus too misleads the communities and only
dominant views are heard. So the author suggested third way called as middle
level analysis. He says that instead of addressing the problem from theoretical
angle or providing issue based solution one can have ‘generalized principles
at work in the ethical analysis’ through a form of dialogue. But in dialogue
someone decides on what basis or principle the dialogue can happen and how to
have a dialogue. So the dialogue in my opinion is determined by unequal position
of the actors which is not explained well by Penz.
The
author used three normative principles such as utilitarianism, libertarianism
and egalitarianism and states that we need to have interaction of all the three
in evaluating the project. But he fails to understand innate nature of
technology being socially constructed while describing libertarianism. Also the
much talked about equal sharing perspective in Tsunami context did not bring
benefits to the have nots. So Rawlsian principle of maximizing the condition of
the worst off is still a mirage in Indian condition.
He
also positioned the state and non-state especially the Non Governmental
Organisation while dealing with displacement. He noted that state should act as
a moderator between foreign actors through other state and its own citizens
since it has moral obligation to its own people. Experience shows that state
becomes party to the oppression rather than protecting its own citizens. So
shouldering the entire responsibility on them would undermine the cosmopolitan
ethic. Or is it possible to practice such a model if the state itself is the
promoter of many displacements.
As the author points out is it possible to make the state and non-state to have a moral responsibility for its action. Can we engage the state in a more critical manner by applying ethical principles and what are the mechanisms to check or to make state accountable if it compromises the ethical principle. This should have been the core argument of the article. But the author could not show any concrete mechanism to implement the cosmopolitism based ethics. If we want to engage the state and non-state what would be the role of International Ethics? Here, the question of Sovereignty becomes important. Can the state allow it to be questioned for its action? If so, at what level and in what means? Who can engage the state in a critical way? How about the repressive state? Can Cosmopolitan ethics be practiced in such circumstances? How about the state in partnership with other state and colludes with non-state actors to ensure displacement. The article in my opinion fails to analyze the historicity of displacement starting with colonialism and to neo colonialism. In today’s world the credibility of UN itself questioned. So how far cosmopolitan ethic is practically possible is a question mark.
“Fear” as a factor in the displacement of vulnerable Groups
by Sh. M.S. Yadav
Introduction
More than 80% of the world refugees consist of vulnerable groups of the society,
particularly the women, children, the minority groups.
In this note, I am going to discuss the fear factor in the displacement
of vulnerable groups, how fear contributes in their displacement, what are other
factors which indirectly contributes in this regard.
Displacement
When ever a person is compelled by the prevailing circumstances to leave his
place of living for seeking safety, shelter and other requirements of survival.
This displacement may be within the state and out of the state.
There are number of factors internal and external which create the
situation for a person to leave his home. The
situations like - war, internal disturbance, state oppression, communal
violence, terrorism, development projects, attacks on culture & ideology
etc. Such displaced person can be
either given shelter / food etc. in the refugee camp or can be repatriated.
In all the situations mentioned above, the most sufferers are the
vulnerable groups.
Convention
of 1951 Speaks of “well founded fear” on the ground of determination of
refugees / of displaced person. The
punishment experienced, pain and suffering faced by the individual on his own
body, his family members, the group of his society and substantial risks
involved to their existence. The
quantum of fear for future dangers can also be the ground of seeking shelter.
However,
if fear is well founded, it must match up with the language of law, justice and
the judge. If the refugee is
inarticulate is not in fear. The
outcome of this translation of fear into knowledge and then reason, is the
extreme in justice to one who is in fear and has sought shelter.
The extreme form of justice where on one hand fear may not lead to care
as it was inadequate to be deserving of care when measured legally.
The
correct measurement of fear and danger to vulnerable groups is also sometime not
fully explained to the shelter provider or measured by them.
It needs institutionalized and careful consideration, otherwise it will
double the suffering of displaced person.
The
another fear factor contributing for displacement of vulnerable group , is that
when the Govt suppress the mass movement by use of security forces, the male
family members are put behind the bar and under fear of cruel treatment and
sexual exploitation by the State representative, the female members with
children flee from the region for a destination by crossing the borders.
Though
they crossed the border under fear to save them from atrocities of the
particular group or State Authorities yet they remain under fear of deportation
as they did not face the trauma and had flee in anticipation of repressive
actions. They do not travel with
relevant document of citizenship etc. and it becomes difficult to justify their
demand for the grant of status of refuges.
Whenever,
there is a communal clash in one part of the country or the religious
fundamentalist comes to power, the minority groups in particular area are
targeted and the fear again compels them to flee for safety and shelter, as
reportedly happened in Bangladesh where Hindu were targeted.
Examining
the international community’s progress in implementing security regulation
(1325) on women, on peace and society, two independent experts appointed by
UNIFEN found that women are effective agent of peace but still they have little
excess to power and peace negotiation. At
the same time, they are sufferer of the atrocities of perpetrators. The
fear of rape / sexual exploitation always contributes to their displacement.
In
the area dominated by terrorists, the young people are forced to join their
cadre, the ladies / girls are sexually exploited.
The families who do not allow their young children / male person to join
terrorist cadre, such family has to face their brutal repercussions.
Fear of such actions also causes ladies to leave such area with their
other family members. When the
terrorist groups recruits ladies in their cadres, the receiving state hesitates
and sometime declares no entry zone. When Sh. Rajiv Gandhi was assassinated
by a women suicide bomber, the female refugees were subjected to
intensive scrutiny.
The
hardship of eviction and resettlement are always not shared equally.
In case of Tehri Dam Project in India, compensation payments have been
mostly paid to the male heads. The
National Commission for Women conducted a survey on displaced in the Tehri Dam
Project and found that terms of rehabilitation were extremely modest, even then
it was not fully implemented. The fear of insecurity among the women still
exists as the share of property is not in the name of female.
The
fear of not getting the refugees status for want of justified grounds and legal
papers, the displaced vulnerable groups prefers to live outside the refugee
camps and has to face the deprival of all benefits of such camps and has to live
in further displaced condition.
On
the basis of above discussion, it can be safely presumed that vulnerable groups
i.e. women, children and ethenic minorities are the most sufferer of the wars,
internal disturbances, ethenic violence, group clashes, state repressions,
terrorist actions and fundamentalism. The
women who are soft target for sexual exploitation, discrimination in all spheres
of life and hold the responsibility of children, are the most sufferers.
The fear of insecurity and the responsibility of looking after the
children compel them to flee for a safer place in above conditions.
However, the quantum of fear and suffering faced by the individual should not be the main criteria for recognizing the refugee’s status of an individual. The UNHCR and State Authorities should also consider the anticipated potential threats to the person who is seeking the asylum particularly the vulnerable groups. The provisions for providing protection and relief to the displaced person needs to be Institutionalized and Synchronized with the legal provisions. However, in no way it should be allowed as a base camp for waging a war against a democratic secular state in the name of independence or ideological values. The anticipated fear to the displaced groups should be gauged on the basis ground realities and measures should be adopted to prevent the exploitation within the camps from any angle.
Critically analyse Peter Penz’s article on “Development, Displacement and International Ethics,” and comment how ethical it is to displace people for reasons of development?
by Sanam Roohi
There
is an urgent need to comprehend the significant issue of ethics of care and
justice in the context of migration and displacement. The perception of
caregiver, be it the state or the humanitarian agencies or the NGO’s, differ
among themselves, so does the perception differs in the eye of the recipient of
this care. The victims of displacement due to developmental projects, (either
directly or indirectly, sometimes forced, sometimes apparently a consciously
decided act) requires not just relief and compensation but rehabilitation. There
is a need to understand that what these displaced persons get, are not charity
but it is their right to have a life of dignity. Though there is a need for the
universality of the ethical language of care and justice, there is no unilinear
approach on what the ethical principles and practices should be. To develop this
ethical language, there is a need for a dialogical understanding between the
giver and the recipient of this care.
Peter
Penz’s article argues for a ‘cosmopolitan approach to determining the moral
obligations of foreign participants in the development process’, thereby
legitimising the neo-liberal model of development. Talking on Forced Migration
on account of developmental and environmental projects, he argues that such
migrations are ‘objectionable’ as they make the displaced people ‘worse
off’. Questioning whether displacement can at all be justified, he identifies
three methodologies in applied ethics and identifies the principle of middle
level ‘generalised principled approach’ as ‘attractive’ analysis on the
basis of which he explores the causes of justification of displacement. Marrying
the three normative perspectives of the utilitarian cost benefit analysis, the
self determination perspective of libertarians as well as communitarians and
finally the egalitarian perspective, he finds a comprehensive ethical approach
to this issue.
But
in case of a third world country like India, we had seen how, during the
Nehruvian era, people were ready to undertake the sacrifices for industrial
development, eager to pay the price for the nation as a whole. The cases of
Bhakra Nangal or the Hirakud or any other dams that stoked nationalistic fervour
and asked the people to sacrifice there homes and livelihood for the nation,
have seen them paying the price of their sacrifice, generations later. Today, in
a globalised neoliberalised economy, where the wealth concentration is only
twenty percent among the world’s eighty percent of the population, we not only
see that sometimes the cost benefit analysis is so calculated to benefit the
investors (mostly foreign) or the donor countries or other non-state actors.
Consent is not only produced but often forced, and the egalitarian and
democratic nature of the projects which aim to benefit ‘all’ is a complete
misnomer. It renders the displaced in a vicious cycle of deprivation and
suffering. In the past few months, certain Indian states like Orissa, West
Bengal and Andhra Pradesh (which have attracted huge FDI’s and private
investments that require huge amount of land acquisition, frequently agrarian
and forest land), has led to many resistances, often leading to violence,
against such misconstrued acquisitions.
People
no longer are ready to rise up to the nationalistic demands on issues that are
responsible in producing situations and conditions that have push settled life
to an unsettling experience of homelessness. In India, as elsewhere in South
Asia,
the process of displacement without the consent of the affected persons can
result in their marginalisation, which goes ‘beyond material impoverishment to
the deprivation of the social, cultural and psychological infrastructure that
has sustained the communities.’ The manner in which they are deprived of their
sustenance and its source, largely without their consent usually render them
incapable of taking their own decisions. This aspect is important to bear in
mind because around 80 percent of the DP/PAPs belong to subaltern communities
such as tribals, Dalits and the poorest among the backwards[i].
Penz
rightly sees the development projects of the third world as not ‘strictly
national’ but involving foreign actors. Denouncing the role of state, which
often acts against its own citizen, he situates the moral obligation with
‘foreign participants in development’. But in reality, often the state and
the foreign actors collude to engage in projects, which blindly displace people,
giving them compensation by taking away their land, which is often their source
of livelihood. In practice, as we still live very much under an era of ‘sovereigntism’,
the moral obligation does lie with the state as with the business firms and
other non-state actors responsible for causing displacement.
Ranabir Samaddar in his article ‘Power, Fear, Ethics’ has pointed out how power structure in democracies makes groups of people as its victim, which can include the displaced people. He terms it as a question of ‘democratic deficit’. States like India make pledges at the international level to recognise, protect and enforce, fundamental human rights, including right to life which has been interpreted by the Supreme Court as right to life with dignity. So states also have to fulfil these obligations that may arise with any developmental project. But even though the state’s international credibility with organisations like U.N and World Bank might be at risk if these human rights are violated; yet such human rights of individuals and groups can only be claimed from the states. Therefore, there is a need to redefine state’s role and responsibility in rehabilitating the victims of developmental and environmental projects. Since international organisations have no legal authority to enforce the state to observe the human rights, this democratic deficit translates into humanitarian deficit too. We need to have a more comprehensive approach which combines the rights based approach and the humanitarian approach to rehabilitate the victims of displacement and more decisively control such rampant displacements across the developing world from becoming an endemic human disaster.
[i] Fernandes, Walter. 2007. “Singur and the Displacement Scenario,” Economic and Political Weekly, 42 (n. 3, Jan. 20-26, pp. 203-206.