Review relevant
sections on ethics and justice in B.S. Chimni's International Refugee
Law: A Reader and comment on the importance of these two issues in
rehabilitation and care of refugees.
OR
After reading Ranabir Samaddar's article on "Power, Fear,
Ethics," in Refugee Watch critically discuss
"fear" as a factor in the displacement of vulnerable groups.
OR
Critically analyse Peter Penz's article on "Development,
displacement and International Ethics," and comment how ethical it
is to displace people for reasons of development?
Module Note
Why should we care
for and protect the victims of forced displacement? The “we” here
refers to those who have not had experienced displacement themselves,
yet harbour some form of an ethical commitment to the victims of forced
displacement. The ethical language therefore is expected to establish
some form of a connection between us and them, between those who are not
forcibly displaced and those who are. Ethics in other words cannot but
be dialogical. Its language in no way denies agency to the victims.
CRG’s studies in the partition ‘refugees’ in the east, for
example, underline a plethora of self-help initiatives undertaken by
them. Ethical language therefore is a language of universality that cuts
across the given boundaries of the victims’ groups and communities.
While ethical language has to be universal, the phenomenon of forced
displacement is not. It is true that the incidence of forced
displacement has alarmingly been on the rise – thanks to the forces
and processes of globalization, their number is still considerably
smaller than that of the world’s settled population. Much of
what |
|
the displaced
persons do for themselves will not be construed as ethical practice.
Ethics is essentially about the self caring for and holding itself
responsible to the other. Ethics, as Levinas reminds us, ‘will never
in any lasting way be the good conscience of corrupt politics’ (Levinas
1989:295). Caring the other however may be the means of caring for the
self.
As the ethical connection can only be established through dialogues,
that is to say, through arguments and reasoning between the parties
involved in them, the terms of such arguments and reasoning need not be
identical. We care for the displaced persons and our practices of care
and protection may have been issued from diverse foundational
principles. That we differ on the ethical principles does not put an
obstacle to the very act of caring and protecting others. The dialogue
must cut across the established divisions of ethical and moral systems
and elaborates itself in a way that it does not remain captive to any
given modality of ethical practice. While plurality of such systems and
modalities is helpful in building the much-needed ‘consensus’ around
these principles, rigour and coherence in our arguments and reasoning
may more often than not turn out to be a liability for those who feel
committed to the care and protection of the displaced persons. That is
the reason why scholars like Peter Penz argue for more self-consciously
uncertain and middle-level theories of ethics. [1]
The importance of ‘moral reasoning’ in initiating organized
responses can hardly be exaggerated. That the principles underline the
necessity of organized responses does not mean that there are no
unorganized (like, the reflexive and instinctual) responses at all to
the problem under review. But we must keep in mind that the organized
and unorganized responses take on two rather distinct ethical
trajectories. Most of the empirical studies on unorganized, altruistic
responses in general (not necessarily towards the displaced persons)
seem to indicate their un-self-conscious character. That is to say,
those who care for and protect are not at the same time
|