vary if it ever
becomes a necessary condition for the enjoyment of one’s non-derogable
rights including that to life. What if it becomes impossible to carry
out displacement without simultaneously violating ‘the rights to life
and freedom from cruel, inhuman or degrading treatment’? What if
displacement involves violation of the victims’ right to life and
livelihood? Displacement in that case is bound to be illegal for it
leads to derogation of an otherwise non-derogable right enshrined in the
Constitution or law. By basing itself on the rights-based argument, the
ethics of care and protection remains beholden to the contingent nature
of the relationship between the right against displacement on one hand
and any of the non-derogable rights recognized by the court of law on
the other. An argument is often made to locate the rights of the
displaced persons within ‘a radical democratic perspective’, bravely
redefine the lines of derogability and non-derogability and thereby
extend the sphere of their rights beyond the given limits of law by
constantly waging and organizing political struggles (Jayal 1998). This
in fact turns the rights-based argument by its head by basing rights on
ethics and ethical reasoning and not vice versa.
This takes us to the heart of our second argument. According to it, care
and protection always follow the established lines of community and
kinship. Organizing responses beyond these lines proves particularly
difficult especially in South Asia where community and kinship ties are
found to be exceptionally strong. The community-based argument evidently
has its limits: in course of organizing the responses, it not only
reinforces the traditional lines of rivalry, but reenacts the inequities
and asymmetries otherwise internal to these bodies. Various reports
emphasize how life in camps, allocation and utilization of aid and
assistance for the displaced persons reinforce the kinship and community
lineages and become the fertile ground for future tensions and ethnic
strife. |
|
The limits of the
community-based argument are sought to be overcome by what we call, the
humanitarian argument. A somewhat old-fashioned version of the argument
looks upon care and protection as a form of ‘moral exercise’ that we
require for making our individual selves ‘pure and perfect’. Helping
others according to this version is a form of self-help, of achieving
one’s higher moral self. The objective of self-help does not however
rule out the necessity of organized responses. Learning to work with
others is also a means of helping oneself and the proponents of this
argument recognize the importance of institutions and organizations in
accomplishing this objective. Today however, the humanitarian ethics
seldom turns on one’s own self. It instead considers others as equal
ethical agents in the sense that they are as much entitled to ‘purity
and perfection’ as we are. Viewed in this light, our care and
protection are a tribute to their ethical entitlements, of which they
are otherwise deprived.
Humanitarian ethics thus has two presuppositions: first, displacement in
South Asia cannot be fathomed without the metaphor of home for it is not
simply where we live or to which all of us are morally entitled like
many other objects of our social existence, but it is the fountainhead
of all our moral and ethical entitlements. Almost all the South Asian
societies make a distinction between the home we simply live in and the
home (e.g. ghar in Marathi or aamar gharkhon in Assamese) that helps
shape what we aspire to become and therefore invest us with our moral
identities. Any involuntary displacement is a disjuncture between home
and home, between what we are and what we want to become, between our
senses of lack and fulfillment. Secondly, should a conflict arise
between our and their moral entitlements, humanitarian ethics always
settles for a minimalist course. Those of us who have the commitment to
and power of taking care and protecting the displaced persons
|